|
Goals
and Means in Law
Csaba Varga
Pázmány
University – Faculty of Law, Hungary
[Abstract]
Papal encyclicals and their interest in the value-implementation
rather than the mere self-fulfilment of the formalistic schemes
of democracy, parliamentarism, human rights and of the overall
setup of legal instrumentality are examined in parallel with the
duality of contradicting arguments in legal technique, focussing
on either formal consequence or materialisation in contents,
such as ones by Shammaď
vs. Hillel, Labeo
vs. Capito,
moreover, Kelsen
vs. Schmitt, as well as positivism versus post-war
Radbruch.
Conceiving of law as both craftsmanship and arts, i.e., ars
in Latin, presents law in a state of equilibrium from the
very beginning, in which the questions of “wherefrom?” and
“along what standards?” to start reasoning are complemented by
those of “where to?” and “arriving at what result?” to channel
reasoning. Genuine use of legal technique may help in that
continuous pondering and balancing, together with the
subordination of institutional operation to the cause of the
person, his family and nation, taken as the reproductive
community for the development of the person and his dignity,
will be increasingly realised in everyday judicial practice.
In the field of jurisprudence, it was pointed
out by the research of, e.g.,
Friedrich Carl von Savigny,
François Gény,
Jean Dabin and
others
that in the course of its application, law can only be actualised as contextualised in one or another setting,
by the use of given legal techniques. However, given that
reductio ad infinitum is impossible, the technique of
law-application not only defies further normative definition but
enables applications with equal chances in logic that point to
expressly opposite and practically mutually excluding
directions.
Option for inclusio or exclusio, argumentum a
simile or argumentum e contrario, analogia or
want of it, searching for a basic underlying identity or marking
a difference—this is what Civil Law and Common Law justices are
used to deciding on at all times in their professional life, be
their legal cultures based on posited rules, on guiding casual (precedental)
decision or on finding a formula (writ) outlining in what and
how to proceed. But the answer to their query in what way to act
and proceed will be quite simple: they act by following
patterns—as long as they can; then, by resorting to their own
decisions—when there is no pattern available to provide
guidance.
Therefore, for its practical materialisation,
law depends to a considerable extent on the mode of selecting
out and actualising those technical and intepretive,
argumentative and evidentiary means and procedures that are
accepted in law to both shape and channel the formation of the
judge’s final conviction, over which the law has no control any
longer. Owing to such mediators being wedged in the process, the
reifying power of the law gets back into the hand of man (with
no relief any longer from his personal responsibility), who has
equal chance to use or misuse (under-use or over-use) the law,
making more or less optimum use, as the case may be, of his
predecessors’ heritage and his own talent.
For this very reason, our theoretical
interest in and responsibility for the workings of law can by
far not stop at the point where the law is posited. Just like
“law in books” [somewhat as a Ding an sich] becomes
tangible for us [as a Ding für uns] in the reality of the
“law in action”,
law cannot be considered otherwise than a process. And taken as
a process, law works
in function of its environment and can only be assessed through
its conditioning and contextualising culture.
*
The philosophy placing the person in the
centre as formulated by the Supreme Pontiff John Paul II during
His philosopher’s life earlier in Poland and which became
integrated within the social teaching of the Church by now,
reflects methodologically similar insights regarding
institutional operation in general. Notably,
“Man cannot
relinquish himself or the place in the visible world that
belongs to him; he cannot become the slave of things, the slave
of economic systems, the slave of production, the slave of his
own products. A civilization purely materialistic in outline
condemns man to such slavery”,
“What is in
question is the advancement of persons, not just the multiplying
of things that people can use. It is a matter […] not so much of
»having more« as of »being more«.”
And it is man at all times who bears
responsibility for this all, which he may not in the least shift
to man-created institutions, superstructure or society. Not any
given arrangement of any certain human community is a purpose in
and for itself. And it cannot be used as a self-justification
either. We have to be aware that
“Human rights and
the rights of God go hand in hand.”
All our call-words
and the institutions constructed by humans are fruits of man’s
striving for good, of man’s struggles and partial successes to
the extent that man has indeed every reason to protect the
products of his efforts. However, the significance of all such
fruits cannot lie in themselves but exclusively in the values
they may assist to implement. Man’s ultimate evangelical purpose
is not just to devise instruments but to properly serve the
human personality and its unalienable dignity here on Earth,
through developing the suitable media to care for them. To quote
just one example,
“In fact, democracy
itself is a means and not an end, and »the value of a democracy
stands or falls with the values which it embodies and
promotes«.”
This same relation of goals and means (with
the latter necessarily subordinated to the former) arises also
in connection with the evaluation of world-wide integration into
one unity, as one of the main tendencies underlying our age and
determining our future.
“Globalization,
a priori, is neither good nor bad. It will be what people
make of it. No system is an end in itself, and it is necessary
to insist that globalization, like any other system, must be at
the service of the human person; it must serve solidarity and
the common good.”
Obviously, if
“globalization is ruled merely by the laws of the market applied
to suit the powerful, the consequences cannot but be negative.”
The outcome seems evident if, as illustrated by the Papal
examples, the effect of globalisation manifests itself in
“absolutizing the economy, unemployment, the reduction and
deterioration of public services, the destruction of the
environment and natural resources, the growing distance between
rich and poor, unfair competition which puts the poor nations in
a situation of ever increasing inferiority.”
No institution is
therefore innocent by itself and no institution carries its
value alone in its self. The only reason for institutional
existence can be the service of humans in the sense that
“the person in the
community [...] must, as a fundamental factor in the common
good, constitute the essential criterion for all programmes,
systems and regimes.”
Searching even
deeper for the core of the “internal need” or “interior demand
of the human being”,
at the service of which human efforts shall be aimed, we
inevitably arrive at the realm of values: values which we
ourselves have to reveal and identify in the created world,
based on our own culture, experienced and continuously improved,
helping us orient ourselves in the world, in which we move by
giving an account of our existence as humans. All this testifies
to an unchallengeable priority amongst values. In terms of this,
we can agree that
“Ethics demands
that systems be attuned to the needs of man, and not that man be
sacrificed for the sake of the system. […] Globalization must
not be a new version of colonialism. It must respect the
diversity of cultures which […] are life’s interpretive keys”.
Aware of some contemporary threats, the Pope asserts that what
is desirable as an outcome is “not […] a single dominant
socio-economic system or culture which would impose its values
and its criteria on ethical reasoning”,
that is, “not […] absolute relativization of values and the
homogenization of life-styles and cultures”.
It is the person’s
decision about his own life with respect to the principle of
subsidiarity that is absolutely vital. And this also involves
the respect of the levels of decision for that sovereignty can
be realised on both an individual and a statal plane.
“The essential
sense of the State, as a political community, consists in that
the society and people composing it are master and sovereign of
their own destiny. This sense remains
unrealized
if, instead of the
exercise of power with the moral participation of the society or
people, what we see is the imposition of power by a certain
group upon all the other members of the society.”
In the light of the teaching, even the
achievements of several centuries of our Euro-Atlantic
development, taken for granted so far as democracy,
parliamentarism and human rights are,
can in themselves be hardly conceived of as anything more than
faceless techniques. Or, they are nothing but neutral
instruments in se and per se, carrying values
exclusively through the realisation of goals to the service of
which they have once been invented..
Yet, if this is the case, they can only be taken as universal
(or are suitable to universalisation) as abstract
potentialities, for exclusively the depth of how they actually
fill their roles under hic et nunc given conditions may
qualify their concrete materialisation eventually good,
beneficial or exemplary. Whether our duty is to operate or
develop (by deepening or extending or reconsidering) them, as
may be required at a given time, we must not forget that they
are only justifiable to the extent they encourage the
development of the person directly or indirectly.
We have to be aware of the fact that none of
them does prevail by itself as part of the nature or as an
entity destined from the outset to share or shape humans’ lives.
For instance,
“Democracy, as an
idea as well as a practice, does not come by itself; it is
neither an intellectual evidence nor a spontaneous behavior. On
the contrary […].”
All these are artificial human constructions,
skills developed through the constantly controlled experience
accumulated through generations,
sustained and substantiated by the unceasing human effort at
socialisation, re-generation and re-conventionalisation.
Examining the lessons drawn from anthropology
in the perspective of the history of philosophy,
we may arrive at a reconstruction according to which the person (including his personality and individuality) can only
develop in human history as conditioned by forms of association
that are indispensable for the biological as well as the social
reproduction of humankind, known—in want of better
identification of types—as the
family as well as the
nation. Person, his/her family and nation: these are the
basic constituents to be taken as axiomatic foundations,
successively building upon one another as balanced in their
mutual preconditioning and support. Therefore, no external
limitation (even in the name of such usually absolutised human
values as freedom and self-determination) can be imposed upon
and to the detriment of any of them. In consequence, any other
specifically human value is thus reflexive upon and instrumental
to them—in function of the optimum development of the person and
his/her family and nation.
Obviously, family and nation, as media of
humans’ societal reproduction, are instrumental for the person
to develop with dignity realised. Human rights, fundamental
freedoms as well as the legal values of freedom and
self-determination are instrumental to the former.
Finally, the values of legal formalism such as legal security,
equality before the law or the law’s foreseeability, are
instrumental as merely formal mediatory values to all the above
foundational values.
Thus, the purport of institutional operation
is necessarily more than the destiny of itself; therefore, it
cannot be controlled, qualified or justified merely by reference
to and in terms of its institutional constitution. The
observance of a set of rules defining institutional operation in
its formalised homogeneity is only sufficient for the operation
in question to be qualified as complying with its own rules but
not for anything more or else. No doubt, institutions are
expected to operate regularly, however, certainly they have not
been established for the very reason to be regular for their own
sake (so to say, in a l’art pour l’art way). On the
whole, something far more is at stake here than the one
suggested by “the doctrine of the supremacy of the greater
number, and that all right and all duty reside in the majority”.
For “The imperium of truth is not and cannot be democratic.”
Each and every institution points beyond its own self.
“Democracy does not itself introduce values, nor does democracy
itself produce values. It mediates between values.”
The institution is intermediary in assisting to implement
imported values in their respectively professional homogenised
fields.
Thus, institutional
existence cannot be taken as an in itself sufficient totality.
Its homogenised operation is only intended to maximise its
instrumental efficiency. However, there is a price to be paid
for this. For the institution as such will be dependent on
external factors and, if getting into improper hands or into the
attraction of improper intentions, it may become exposed to all
kinds of uncontrollable powers. This is the underlying reason
why the Social Teaching of the Catholic Church has to emphasise
in describing the interrelation between large systems that
“if there is no
ultimate truth to guide and direct political activity, then
ideas and convictions can easily be manipulated for reasons of
power. As history demonstrates, a democracy without values
easily turns into open or thinly disguised totalitarianism.”
Consequently, the human person with his own
personal faith, conscience, values and conviction shall not be
neglected. Likewise, personal responsibility with the ethos of
moral commitment and the predisposition for re-consideration
(adaptation and response to new challenges) any time when needed
is part of the scheme.
*
Approaching legal dilemmas with such a
sensitivity, what we can see is that due to the inherent
polarity arising from the law’s formalism, the development of
legal thought (both in judicial practice and legal scholarship)
often takes place through generating (positing)
in themselves utterly artificial
antithetical concepts which may then abruptly switch over
into one another. The conflicts, for instance, of
Shammaď and
Hillel in classical Jewish law or of the
Proculians and the
Sabinians
(following Labeo
and Capito respectively) in Roman law equally illustrate the
collision of form and
contents with their emphasis on strictness of
being tied to the text, on the one hand, and the
liveability of the entire regulatory arrangement with the
realisation of the originally contemplated goals in mind, on the
other.
Moreover, listing more examples up to the tragic recent past of
20th-century European history, the controversy
between Hans Kelsen
and Carl Schmitt
during the Weimar crisis can—apart from their positions being
thoroughly twisted under the constraint of conditions—also be
construed as the (equally dangerous, if taken as exclusive)
alternative of either a purely
formal procedurality justifying any result (maybe
destroying even the last chance of national advancement) from
the outset or a substantivity
calling for a sovereign decision with the expectation of
being able to finally reach the underlying goal.
Or, the conditional acceptance of formal requirements, that is,
the justification of procedurally defined paths exclusively in
function of their suitability for achieving the actual purpose
(with searching for the mutuality of satisfactory balances
instead of the one-sidedness of exclusivities) is all but new
recognition in the history of legal thought.
This is what presents the application of any norm in the context
of the pondering between the goods to be protected and the goals
to be achieved, just as
Jesus Christ did, when He declared, as against the
Pharisean interpretation of the Sabbath’s law: “So it is lawful
to do good on the sabbath”.
The dramatic self-transcendence by
Gustav Radbruch—who
had to realise on the ruins of the Third Reich that his earlier
dedication to security in law might destruct the basic need of
justice, moreover, it might also leave the damages caused by the
facts of crying injustice both unremedied and unremediable in
the law—served
as an empirical proof for him and for us all that any
one-sidedness (no matter how eternal and guaranteed the human
principles involved seem) may have a destructive impact upon
law. The solution is obviously not just stumbling about between
the extremes but pondering upon the ancient Roman wisdom.
Namely, conceiving of law as both craftsmanship and arts, i.e.,
‘ars’ in Latin, presents law in a state of
equilibrium from the very beginning, in which both the questions
of “wherefrom?” and “along what standards?” to start reasoning
as well as those of “where to?” and “arriving at what result?”
to channel reasoning are of complementary
and equal importance.
After all, reasoning started from
somewhere has to be channelled in a considered and continuously
re-considered perspective.
In fact, the consciousness of the genuine
purport of legal technique in law may help us to achieve that
such a continuous meditation, pondering and balancing on and
amongst various aspects, values and interests with the
subordination of all kinds of institutional operation (and their
inherent strive for alienation) to the service of the cause of
the person, his family and nation as a community home will be
increasingly realised in everyday practice.
Scientific advisor at the Institute for Legal Studies
of the Hungarian Academy of Sciences, Professor of the
Faculty of Law of the Pázmány Péter Catholic University
of Hungary, Director of its Institute for Legal Philosophy
(H–1428 Budapest 8, P. O. Box 6 [
varga@jak.ppke.hu
].
‘Address of the Holy Father’ in Globalization Ethical
and Institutional Concern [Proceedings, Seventh Plenary
Session, 25–28 April 2001] ed. Edmond Malinvaud & Louis
Sabourin (Vatican City 2001), p. 28 [The Pontifical Academy
of Social Sciences, Acta 7].
‘Address of the Holy Father’ in Globalization (note
11), p. 29. As an American author—Thomas L. Friedman The
Lexus and the Olive Tree [New York:
Farrar, Straus &
Giroux
1999] rev. ed. (2000), p. 302, quoted by Mary Ann Glendon
‘Meeting the Challenges of
Globalization’
in
ibid. (note 11), p. 338—continues, “You cannot build an
emerging society […] if you are simultaneously destroying
the cultural foundations that cement your society and give
it the self-confidence and cohesion to interact properly
with the world […]. For without a sustainable culture there
is no sustainable community and without a sustainable
community there is no sustainable
globalization.”
See, e.g., Democracy Some Acute Questions [The
Proceedings of the Fourth Plenary Session of the Pontifical
Academy of Social Sciences, 22–25 April 1998] ed. Hans F.
Zacher
(Vatican
City 1999) 450 pp. [Pontificiae
Academiae Scientiarum Socialium
Acta 4] and
Democracy Reality and Responsibility (note 10).
See,
above all, Chaďm
Perelman
‘Legal Ontology
and Legal Reasoning’ Israel Law Review 16 (1981) 3, pp.
356–367 and
Peter Stein
‘Logic and Experience in Roman and Common Law’ Boston
University Law Review
59
(1979) 3, pp.
433–451 {reprinted in Comparative Legal Cultures ed.
Csaba Varga (Aldershot, Hong Kong, Singapore, Sydney:
Dartmouth & New York: The New York University Press 1992)
xxiv + 614 pp. [The International Library of Essays in Law &
Legal Theory, Legal Cultures 1], pp. 363 et seq. et 333 et
seq., respectively}.
Cf., from the author, ‘Change
of Paradigms in Legal Reconstruction (Carl Schmitt and the
Temptation to Finally Reach a Synthesis)’ in
Perspectives on
Jurisprudence
Essays in Honor of Jes Bjarup, ed. Peter Wahlgren
(Stockholm: Stockholm Institute for Scandinavian Law 2005)
[= Scandinavian Studies in Law 48], pp. 517–529 &
Rivista internazionale di Filosofia del Diritto LXXXI
(ottobre / dicembre 2004) 4, pp. 691–707.
|
|