Home About International University Project Conferences Courses Lectures Projects Publications Readings Contribute Contact      

home \ projects \ step \ on the law \ question 92 \ article 2

STEP home

Treatise on Law

Conferences

Essays

Scholars

Related links

 

 


 
 
STEP - St. Thomas Education Project
 
     
 
<<<   ARTICLE   >>>
 
 

ST. THOMAS AQUINAS

 

ON THE LAW

 

SUMMA THEOLOGIAE

FIRST PART OF THE SECOND PART (I-II)

(Trans. Alfred J. Freddoso)

QUESTION 92

The Effects of Law

ARTICLE 2

 

Are the acts of law correctly enumerated when one says that the acts

of law are to command, to forbid, to permit, and to punish?

 

It seems that the acts of law are not correctly enumerated when one says that the acts of law are to command, to forbid, to permit, and to punish:

 

Objection 1:  As the Jurist [Gratian] says [in Decretum 3], law consists in all the general precepts.  But to command is the same as to issue a precept.  Therefore, the other three acts are superfluous.

        

Objection 2:  As was explained above (a. 1), the effect of law is to lead its subjects to the good.  But a counsel concerns a better good than a precept does.  Therefore, law has more to do with giving counsel than with issuing precepts.

        

Objection 3:  Just as a man is spurred on toward the good by punishments, so too he is spurred on toward the good by rewards. Therefore, just as punishing is counted as an effect of law, so rewarding should be counted as well.

        

Objection 4:  As was explained above (a. 1), the lawmaker’s intention is to make men good.  But one who obeys the law solely out of fear of punishment is not a good man; for as Augustine says, “Even if one does something good out of servile fear, i.e., the fear of punishment, he still has not done anything well.”  Therefore, to punish does not seem to be a property of law.

        

But contrary to this:  In Etymologia 5 Isidore says, “Every law either permits something (e.g., that a brave man may seek a reward), or it prohibits something (e.g., that no one is permitted to seek marriage with a consecrated virgin), or it punishes something (e.g., someone who has committed murder shall be put to death).”

        

I respond:  Just as a spoken proposition (enunciatio) is a dictate of reason in the mode of asserting (enuntiandi), so too a law is a dictate of reason in the mode of issuing a precept (praecipiendi).
Now it is proper to reason to go from one thing to another.  Hence, in the case of the demonstrative sciences, reason induces assent to the conclusion by means of certain principles; in the same way, it induces assent to a precept of the law by means of something.  Now as was explained above (q. 90, a. 1), the precepts of the law concern human acts, which the law directs, and there are three different kinds of human acts:
As was explained above (q. 18, a. 8), some acts, viz., the acts of the virtues, are good because of their genus, and the act of law that is posited with respect to such acts is to command or to issue a precept.  For as Ethics 5 says, law commands all the acts of the virtues.
By contrast, some acts, such as the acts of the vices, are evil because of their genus, and it is characteristic of law to forbid these acts.
On the other hand, some acts are indifferent because of their genus, and it is characteristic of law to permit to these acts.  In addition, all acts that have either just a little goodness or just a little badness can likewise be called indifferent.
Finally, it is through fear of punishment that the law induces obedience to itself, and in this regard to punish is counted as an effect of law.

        

Reply to objection 1:  Just as ceasing to do evil has a certain type of goodness, so too a prohibition is a certain type of precept.  Accordingly, if ‘precept’ is taken broadly, a law may in general be called a ‘precept’.

        

Reply to objection 2:  To give counsel is not an act proper to law, but can also be the act of a private person who does not have the role of making law.  Hence, in 1 Corinthians 7:12, when he is giving a certain counsel, even the Apostle says, “It is I speaking, and not the Lord.”  This is why giving counsel is not posited among the effects of law.

        

Reply to objection 3:  Once again, to reward can be the role of anyone, whereas to punish pertains only to a minister of the law, by whose authority the punishment is inflicted.  And this is why only punishing, and not rewarding, is counted as an act of the law.

 

Reply to objection 4:  Given that someone begins to be accustomed to avoiding evil and doing good because of his fear of punishment, he is sometimes led to enjoy doing good and to do it by his own will.  Accordingly, it is even by punishing that the law results in men being good.

 

 
     

ON THE LAW

ON THE LAW IN GENERAL

I-II, q. 90, The Essence of Law

I-II, q. 91, The Different Kinds of Law

I-II, q. 92, The Effects of Law

THE PARTS OF LAW

Eternal law

I-II, q. 93, Eternal Law

Natural law

I-II, q. 94, The Natural Law

Human law

I-II, q. 95, Human Law

I-II, q. 96, The Force of Human Law

I-II, q. 97, Changes in Human Law

The old law

I-II, q. 98, The Old Law

I-II, q. 99, The Precepts of the Old Law

I-II, q. 100, The Moral Precepts of the Old Law

I-II, q. 101, The Ceremonial Precepts of the Old Law in Themselves

I-II, q. 102, The Causes of the Ceremonial Precepts

I-II, q. 103, The Duration of the Ceremonial Precepts

I-II, q. 104, The Judicial Precepts of the Old Law

I-II, q. 105, The Nature of the Judicial Precepts

The new law

I-II, q. 106, The Law of the Gospel, called the New Law, in Itself

I-II, q. 107, The Relation between the Old Law and the New Law

I-II, q. 108, The Contents of the New Law