|
Giornale
di Metafisica
2/2005
Knowledge
of the Good as Participation in God’s Love
Fulvio Di Blasi
Thomas Aquinas
suggests often, not only that every creature naturally loves
God above all things and more than itself, but also that our
knowledge of the good essentially involves knowledge and love
of God. Let us read, for example, the following passages:
“Because
nothing is good except insofar as it is a likeness and participation
of the highest good, the highest good itself is in some way
desired in every particular good.”
“Every
movement of a will whereby powers are applied to operation
is reduced to God, as a first object of appetite (primum
appetibile) and a first agent of willing (primum volentem).”
“To
know that God exists in a general and confused way is implanted
in us by nature, inasmuch as God is man’s beatitude.
For man naturally desires happiness, and what is naturally
desired by man must be naturally known to him. This,
however, is not to know absolutely that God exists; just as
to know that someone is approaching is not the same as to
know that Peter is approaching, even though it is Peter who
is approaching; for many there are who imagine that man’s
perfect good which is happiness, consists in riches, and others
in pleasures, and others in something else.”
Now, these are
difficult words that do not seem to fit common morality, in
which apparently God does not play such an important role.
Broadly speaking, we face two possibilities: either Aquinas
was so immersed in abstract metaphysical reflections that
he lost sight of the most ordinary reality, or his metaphysics
expresses in the most radical way the deepest meaning of ordinary
ethical reality. I pick the second. And this is
why I reported the third quotation, in which the idea emerges
that for many—ordinary—people to know and to love God can
just mean to vaguely sense or realize that “someone is approaching.”
In my opinion,
the key concept to understand Aquinas’ view on this issue
is the concept of participation, which I take in this paper
as a purely philosophical concept. The best approach,
accordingly, is to focus first on Aquinas’ general thesis
that every good of this world is not good “essentially” (per
suam essentiam) but by participation. This thesis
entails that knowledge of created goods provides a mediate
knowledge of God as the essential good. The second step
is to focus on our act of knowledge of the good. The
object of this act is the participated good and, through it,
God as the essential good. At the same time, our knowledge
of the good is itself a very special kind of participated
good; its goodness consisting in a formal participation
in God’s knowledge of the good: that is, in His love
of Himself and of creation in view of Himself. In other
words, our act of knowledge of the good has both an objective
aspect and a subjective aspect. Objectively, we know
the good as participated—and thus as objectively revealing
God as the essential good. Subjectively, we are able
to know the participated good due to our formal participation
in God’s love. The third step is to focus on the idea
of “someone approaching,” which alone would deserve more than
an essay, but that here cannot but be limited to a short concluding
remark.
Scholars are
very familiar today with both a wide revival of the concept
of practical knowledge and an intense debate on the concept of ultimate
end in both Aristotle and Aquinas. I should say immediately that in the present
paper I do not want to focus on “practical knowledge” as such
but on “knowledge of the good” generally speaking. The
two concepts are often put together as if they were the same
thing. This is a mistake. Practical knowledge,
at least in Aquinas, is a secondary and specific instance
of knowledge of the good that involves a means-end relationship
in which the end, being actually wanted or desired, makes
the means desirable (dilectio electiva) and becomes
action. Knowledge of the good, simply speaking, is not
practical but speculative. Moreover, the current debate on the ultimate
end appears too narrowly centered on the arguments from intentionality
and from the natural desire given by Aquinas especially in
ST, I-II, q. 1, a. 4 (Is there an Ultimate End for
Human Life?) and q. 3, a. 8 (Does the Happiness of
Man Consist in the Vision of the Divine Essence?).
The present paper does not focus on these arguments either.
There are deeper metaphysical principles at the root of Aquinas’
view on the ultimate end; these principles are, at the moment,
my main concern.
In what follows,
I will first offer a short introduction to the concepts of
“good” and of “participation” (Section 1); these concepts
will be then better elucidated as the paper goes by.
In Section 2, I will address Aquinas’ general thesis of the
created good as participated. Then, in section 3, I
will move toward the analysis of our act of knowledge of the
good. Finally, in section 4, I will return briefly to
the last passage quoted above on our necessary—but general
and confused—knowledge of God.
-
Introducing the Concepts of “Good”
and “Participation”
“Good” (bonum)
is, for Aquinas, a transcendental concept because it signifies
exactly the same reality as “being” (ens). Yet,
the term “good” makes conceptually explicit something that
in the use of “ens” remains implicit. This is
why Aquinas says that “good” adds something to the understanding
of “ens” (super intellectum entis): something
that is not in the things (in rerum natura) but only
in reason (in ratione tantum). Specifically,
“good” adds to “ens” a conceptual reference to the
fact that the ens’ esseis an act, which gives existence and perfection
to the ens, and which is therefore what the ens
itself tends toward. The concept of good, in other words,
contains a conceptual reference to the actual—existing—ens
being always an end and an object of an appetite: “et inde
est quod omnes recte diffinientes bonum ponunt in ratione
eius aliquid quod pertinet ad habitudinem finis.”
This short but
rather technical account reveals an important metaphysical
view of reality. For Aquinas, the existing being is
dynamic: i.e., it is an action and a completion at the same
time. The existing being tends not only toward other
things but also toward its own act; this is why it preserves
itself and remains in existence instead of falling back into
nothingness. Consequently, when we know the existing
being we know it also as good: namely, as an end and the object
of an appetite. Its being good, however, is nothing
else than its esse; and to know the good is nothing
else than to know the way in which things exist, or to know
their act(s)—whether substantial or accidental.
This is why Aquinas writes that “to be in act […] constitutes
the nature of the good (esse igitur actu boni rationem
constituit),” or that “by nature, the good of each thing
is its act and perfection (naturaliter enim bonum uniuscuiusque
est actus et perfectio eius).” This is what we should
keep in mind for the purposes of the present paper: that to
look for “the nature of the good (boni rationem)” is
to look for the “act” and “perfection” of things.
The concept of
participation refers to a specific kind of causality: namely,
the causality that is simultaneously required for the effect
to exist. An example is my hand holding the book: in
this case, when my hand ceases to act as a cause the book
falls down. Another example is the light shining on
the book: when the light ceases to act the book is invisible. Whenever something is acting in a way that
cannot be caused by its own nature, we must logically refer
its action to an external cause able to cause it by essence,
and we say that the relevant object participates in
that cause. The suspended book participates in the power
of my hand, and the visible book participates in the power
of a luminous object. Participation, thus, is something
real in things, and it means a simultaneous and external causal
dependence of their actions or properties. This causal
relation has two important characteristics: (1) that the action
(whatever it is) of the participating object follows the actual
direction given to it by the cause (the suspended book stays
exactly where the hand holds it, and the visible book is visible
according to the kind of light that is acting upon it); (2)
that the action of the participating object makes it similar
to the cause (the suspended book as suspended reveals
something of the power of the hand, and the visible book as
visible is similar to the light-source affecting it).
This can be summarized by saying that, in participation, the
effect as effect is similar to the cause as cause
and obeys its teleology.
As soon as we
focus on the fact that, for Aquinas, the very esse
of things is participated, we can see why the concept of participation
is so important in his metaphysics. For Aquinas, all
things are actually dependent on God as their efficient, final,
and exemplary cause—including rational agents’ act of knowledge
of the good, which act is an accidental perfection of their
being. Hence, the thesis that our act of knowledge of
the good is participated entails: [1] that God simultaneously
causes it as knowledge of the good (participation in God as
efficient cause); [2] that our act involves love of the same
ultimate end that God loves in causing it (participation in
God as final cause); and [3] that our knowledge of the good
is similar to God’s own knowledge of the good (participation
in God as exemplary cause).
-
Created Good as Participated
In De Veritate,
q. 21, a. 5, Aquinas, following “Augustinum, Boetium et
auctorem libri De Causis,” explains that the created good
is said to be participated in a threefold way: as to the accidental
good; as to the essential or substantial good; and as to the
order to the first cause (secundum ordinem ad causam primam).
Aquinas puts the accidental good first because, for him, something
is said to be good absolutely speaking due, not to its substantial
being, but to its accidental being. For my purposes,
however, it is better to follow an ontological order and start
with the essential or substantial good.
2.1. Substantial
Good as Participated
The essential
good of something is the act, or esse, that makes it
existent according to its nature (man, tree, etc.).
The essential principles of each ens, explains Aquinas,
are what make it perfect in order for it to exist—“In se
ipso autem aliquid perficitur ut subsistat per essentialia
principia.” As I just mentioned, Aquinas adds that,
as far as these principles are concerned, something is good
only secundum quid because a creature, in order to
be good absolutely speaking, must be good (or in act)
according to both the essential and the accidental principles.
[An existing human being, for example, is certainly good according
to the act of existence of his nature but can still be either
morally good or morally evil. When we say, “This is
a good man!,” we refer, simply speaking, to his moral personality.]
This is not my focus, though. My focus is on participation.
Why is the creature’s essential good participated? The
answer to this question is that, except in the case of God,
the essence of things does not logically include their existence;
otherwise their natures could give existence to themselves
and they would never die or be corrupted. It is logically
possible to think of a man as not existent. Thus, when
a man exists, it means that his esse participates in
what possesses esse by essence; and this can only be
God. The esse of limited beings is like
the visibility of the book; if God ceases to create the book
disappears. The esse of limited beings,
as the result of God’s creative action, is both similar to
God’s esse and ordered to the end for the sake of which
God creates.
2.2. Accidental
Good as Participated
More difficult
appears the question of the accidental good, because accidents
by definition exist, not in themselves, but in the substance’s
act. In point of fact, to say that the accidents’ good
participates in the substance’s good—which is in turn participated—does
not look very interesting; and Aquinas’ discussion in De
Veritate, q. 21, a. 5 seems to be no more than a homage
paid to a statement made by Augustine. However, the
same thesis is strongly restated in ST, I, q. 6, a.
3; and without any explicit reference to Augustine.
This fact calls for more attention to the relevant text in
De Veritate, q. 21, a. 5; particularly where Aquinas
writes, “Now it is by its essential principles that a thing
is fully constituted (perficitur) in itself so that
it subsists; but it is not so perfectly constituted as to
stand as it should in relation to everything outside itself
(ut debito modo se habeat ad omnia quae sunt extra ipsium)
except by means of accidents added to the essence, because
the operations by which one thing is in some sense joined
to another proceed from the essence through powers distinct
from it. Consequently nothing achieves goodness absolutely
unless it is complete in both its essential and its accidental
principles.”
Aquinas sees
the accidents as the metaphysical principles that relate the
ens to the other things external to it (ad omnia
quae sunt extra ipsum). Movement, for example, is
always an interaction. But we might also think of color
as the relation between the visible objects and the sense
of sight; or of mass as the attractive relation of material
bodies with each other; or even of our intelligence as the
relation of our mind with every other reality (including ourselves
as reflexively known to us). Now, a principle connecting
the existence of two or more things with each other—i.e.,
making them co-exist in the same universe—cannot come
from one of them unless this one is the creator of the other(s).
So, the fact that limited things interact with each
other due to their accidents calls for a transcendent cause
in which they participate as interacting with each other:
that is to say, according to their accidents. If I understand
Aquinas correctly on this point, the metaphysical principle
grounding his idea of the accidental good as participated
coincides with his key idea that there is an order
in nature: namely, that things act naturally in a way that
is at the same time intelligible and harmonious. Aquinas
always explains this point by referring to the notions of
‘part’ and ‘whole.’ His point is very refined because
to say that there is an order means exactly to say that there
is a whole in which things make sense as parts. And
this, in turn, means, not only that the good of the whole
as such is the ultimate meaning of the good of the parts as
parts, but also that every part must be inclined to the good
of the whole before and more than to its own good as part.
After all, this is the reason for the existence of the specific
movement of each part: to contribute to the existence
of the whole. If this were not so, the order itself
(the whole) could not exist.
Whatever we might
think of this argument, Aquinas takes it very seriously.
This is why he states that all creatures, including men and
angels, love God before themselves and with a greater love.
“Not only man, so long as his nature remains unimpaired (in
suae integritate naturae), loves God above all things
and more than himself, but also every single creature, each
in its own way, i.e. either by an intellectual, or by a rational,
or by an animal, or at least by a natural love, as stones
do, for instance, and other things bereft of knowledge, because
each part naturally loves the common good of the whole more
than its own particular good. This is evidenced by its
operation, since the principal inclination of each part is
toward common action conducive to the good of the whole.
It may also be seen in civic virtues whereby sometimes the
citizens suffer damage even to their own property and persons
for the sake of the common good.” In ST, I, q. 60, a. 5, more or less
with the same words, the same principle is specifically applied
to the natural inclination, or natural love, of the will of
both men and angels: “Consequently, since God is the universal
good, and under this good both man and angel and all creatures
are comprised, because every creature in regard to its entire
being naturally belongs to God, it follows that from natural
love angel and man alike love God before themselves and with
a greater love.” It might be helpful to recall that the existence
of a natural order is also the starting point of the fifth
way to prove the existence of God—which, in turn, coincides
with the philosophical proofs given by Aquinas for the existence
of providence and of the eternal law.
2.3. “Secundum Ordinem ad
Causam Primam”
“A still further
difference is discovered between the divine goodness and that
of creatures. Goodness has the character of a final
cause. But God has this, since He is the ultimate end
of all beings just as He is their first principle. From
this it follows that any other end has the status or character
of an end only in relation to the first cause (secundum
ordinem ad causam primam), because a secondary cause does
not influence the effect unless the influence of the first
cause is presupposed, as is made clear in The Causes.
Hence too, good, having the character of an end, cannot be
said of a creature unless we presuppose the relation of Creator
to creature (ordine creatoris ad creaturam).” The key words here are,
“because a secondary cause does not influence the effect unless
the influence of the first cause is presupposed.” This
principle is more explicit in CG, book 3, ch. 17, “Now,
the supreme agent does the actions of all inferior agents
by moving them all to their actions and, consequently, to
their ends. Hence, it follows that all the ends of secondary
agents are ordered by the first agent to His own proper end.
Of course, the first agent of all things is God […]
There is no other end for His will than His goodness, which
is Himself […] Therefore, all things […] are ordered
to God as to their end.”
In order to understand
Aquinas on this point we must remember that the concept of
good involves the appetite for an end. Now, except in
the case of God—in Whom there is no real distinction between
His appetite and His being—, appetite implies movement;
and every movement, in Aristotle and Aquinas’ metaphysics,
requires participation in a first Unmoved Mover. It
goes without saying that when God moves something, He cannot
but do it according to His end, which is Himself. And
it goes without saying that at stake here are not the extrinsic
movements of things, but the intrinsic movements of their
beings: that is to say, their natural inclinations. This same argument is
specifically applied by Aquinas also to the human will, which
under this respect is not different from any other participated
appetite—for “to give natural inclinations is the sole prerogative
of Him Who has established the nature. So also, to incline
the will to anything is the sole prerogative of Him Who is
the cause of the intellectual nature.” Therefore, if it is true that our moving
world requires an Unmoved Mover, it necessarily follows that
every nature—or natural inclination—and every appetite depends
on God as “a first agent of willing (primum volentem)”
(efficient cause) and tend to God “as a first object of appetite
(primum appetibile) (final cause).”
-
Our Knowledge of the Good as Participated
Let us shift
our focus now to our act of knowledge of the good. On
the basis of what was explained above, we should already be
able to conclude that, as an accidental perfection of our
being, this act is a participation in the order God gave to
creation. As such, it tends chiefly to God as to the
end of the whole of creation: that is to say, through this
act we love God before ourselves and with a greater love.
Moreover, as our knowledge of the good involves the movement
of an appetite, it requires the creative action of God as
Unmoved Mover. Thus, it participates in God as “a first
agent of willing” and tends to God “as a first object of appetite.”
So far so good.
However, as correct as these conclusions might be theoretically,
they do not look very satisfactory when what is at stake is
an act as complex as our act of knowledge of the good.
Unquestionably, we need a more specific approach to the nature
of this act and to the supposed need for it to be participated.
And, first of all, we need to focus on what exactly “knowledge
of the good” means compared with the concept of good in general.
3.1. “Good”
and “Knowledge of the Good”
“Good,” as we
recalled above, means that the ens is always an end
and an object of an appetite—without appetite for an end,
properly speaking, there is no good. “Knowledge,” on
the other hand, means, for both Aristotle and Aquinas, “intentional
possession of a form.” “Knowledge of the good,” accordingly—whether
sentient or intellectual—, must mean “intentional possession
of the form of something as object of an appetite.”
But, in turn, being “knowledge of the good” an act—and therefore
a good—of the knower, it cannot but happen by way of appetite.
“Knowledge of the good,” therefore, means to tend toward the
ens by means of a form [of something as object
of an appetite] intentionally possessed by the agent. In
the knowledge of the good, the possessed form and the inclination
of the appetite coincide.
In the case of
rational beings, “knowledge of the good” means at the same
time: (a) to have an intellectual knowledge of the ens
as object of an appetite; and (b) to tend toward it as intellectually
known, or to love it by way of what we call ‘rational appetite.’
The intellectual knowledge of the good is nothing else than
a sort of inclined knowledge: that is, an appetite
for the ens understood as an end. This is why
Aquinas seems to suggest that to know the good and to will
the good are the same thing: “For, since the understood good
(bonum intellectum) is the proper object of the will,
the understood good is, as such, willed. Now, that which
is understood is by reference to one who understands (intellectum
autem dicitur ad intelligentem). Hence, he who grasps
the good by his intellect (intelligens bonum) is, as
such, endowed with will (volens).”
For my purposes,
it is important to notice that it is our very act of (intellectual)
knowledge of the good—this accidental perfection of our being—that
needs to be participated. As the luminous object participates
as luminous in what possesses the light by essence,
and as every created good participates as appetite for
ens in what is essentially good, so our intellectual knowledge
of the good should formally participate as intellectual
knowledge of the good—that is, as a (rational) appetite
for the ens known as an end—in God’s knowledge as the
cause of every good. This means, in turn, that our participation
must formally happen—at the intellectual level—by way of inclination
to God known as the “first agent of willing” and
as the ultimate end (primum appetibile) of both ourselves
and the whole universe; and also as the exemplary cause of
everything. But, does Aquinas offer any specific argument
in support of these things? The answer is “Yes, the
doctrine of the active intellect!”
3.2. The Need
for the Active Intellect
For both Aristotle
and Aquinas, knowledge, whether sentient or intellectual,
is an actualization of a receiver (or passive) knowing faculty
caused by the act of the known object as knowable. For
instance, the visible object as visible (in act) causes the
act of seeing it in the visual faculty. There are two
important principles at stake here: one is that the object
known must be in act in order to be known; and the other is
that to know is an act of the knowing faculty. We can
think of a file (known object) saved on a floppy disk (knowing
faculty). What we call “file” should exist (be in act)
before—and while—being saved; and the saved file is no more
than the floppy disk configured (actualized) in a particular
way. Now, the reason we need the active
intellect to know the truth (whether theoretical or practical)
is that the universals that our (passive) intellect
receives when it knows things through the senses do not exist
as such—as universals—in the (particular) things known.
In other words, the intelligible objects do not exist as intelligible
except in the intellect that knows them; thus, our intellect
must be able to abstract them (i.e., to turn them from potentiality
into actuality) before receiving them—as if the floppy-disk
had to make the file a file before receiving it into itself
as a file. The key point is that our intellect, in order
to make the intelligible species an intelligible species,
must be already in act as intellect before possessing
any actual knowledge at all. I say “as intellect” because
this first act of the intellect as a knower must be similar
to the known object as known: that is, as intelligible.
Knowledge is always a question of similarity. Strictly
speaking, we can say that the passive intellect does not exist
without any knowledge making it actual, but that the active
intellect is subsistent.
This point should
be clearer if we focus better on the relevant difference between
sense knowledge and intellectual knowledge. In the case
of sense knowledge, the knowing faculty is actualized by the
act of the material thing as perceptible.
[22]
In the case of intellectual knowledge, there
is no act of the material thing as intelligible. If
the material individual thing were in act intelligible it
would not be individual and it would not be material.
Therefore, unlike sense knowledge, in the case of intellectual
knowledge the act of the intelligible object is caused by
the knowing faculty itself. The intellect, in other
words, moves itself by causing the act of the intelligible
object as intelligible in order to receive it as an intelligible
species.
[23]
3.3. The Participation
of the Active Intellect
The reason why
our active intellect requires God’s causality is that it is
a moved mover of what is intelligible. The active
intellect causes the acts of the intelligible objects as intelligible
but does not create their intelligibility. This is why
our intellect is still a receiver of knowledge and
does not know everything already; rather, “it
reaches to the understanding of truth by arguing, with a certain
amount of reasoning and movement. Again it has an imperfect
understanding; both because it does not understand everything
and because, in those things which it does understand, it
passes from potentiality to act”—Human
intellect is “mobile” and “imperfect.”
[24]
As a moved mover of what is intelligible
that knows according to degrees of knowledge, the active
intellect fits the rationale of both the first and the fourth
ways to prove the existence of God given in ST, I,
q. 2, a. 3. That is to say, the existence of the active
intellect requires: (1) the existence of a first intellect
that moves every act of understanding without being moved;
and (2) of an intellect that possesses what is intelligible
at the highest degree, and in which every lower degree of
intellectual knowledge participates. This train of reasoning
is clear in ST, I, q. 79, a. 4; and
it is ultimately the reason that Aquinas thinks the active
intellect receives its “intellectual light” (its first act)
directly from God’s intellect—the active intellect makes us
able partially to see things as
they are in God’s mind.
[25]
For Aquinas,
“ens” is the first notion of intellectual knowledge,
and “ens in universali,” or “ens universale”
(universal being), is the common object of this knowledge.
[26]
The concept of “ens” and the concept
of “intelligibility” go together. To know something
intellectually and to know it as ens (being) are the
same thing; everything is intelligible insofar as it is
(a table, a dog, red, tall, pleasant, Sicilian, etc.).
The analogical notion of ens—analogical because no
specific difference can add something to it as if this something
were not ens—precedes, therefore, every particular
intellectual knowledge and constitutes, so to speak, the glasses
through which we see reality as intelligible.
Hence, to say that our intellect tends to know the truth is
equivalent to say that our intellect tends to know the ens
as ens (i.e., the is of being).
As we saw already,
our knowledge of each particular ens reveals a real
distinction between its being (esse) and its
being something (essence)—“this is a pencil,”
but “is” is not only of the pencil. We have already
focused on the need for the creatures’ esse to participate
in an efficient and final cause that is by essence.
Now we should focus on the need for the creature’s esse
to be an imitation of this cause.
Esse
is common to everything and indeterminate: i.e., it can exist
according to every possible essence. Essence, on the
other hand, in a sense limits the being to a specific way
of being. Every particular knowledge of the ens
reveals, therefore, a limitation of the infinite possibilities
of esse; but it reveals also a real imitation
of what possesses esse by essence. This
corresponds exactly, from the side of our knowledge, to the
way in which, for Aquinas, God knows everything through the
knowledge of Himself: “the divine essence comprehends within
itself the nobilities of all beings […] according to the mode
of perfection. Now, every form, both proper and common
[…] is a certain perfection […] The intellect of God
therefore, can comprehend in His essence that which is proper
to each thing by understanding wherein the divine essence
is being imitated and wherein each thing falls short of its
perfection. Thus, by understanding His essence as imitable
in the mode of life and not of knowledge, God has the proper
form of a plant; and if He knows His essence as imitable in
the mode of knowledge and not of intellect, God has the proper
form of animal, and so forth. Thus, it is clear that,
being absolutely perfect, the divine essence can be taken
as the proper exemplar of singulars. Through it, therefore,
God can have a proper knowledge of all things.”
[27]
In short: our
knowledge of (limited) entia reveals their being causally
dependent on what has esse as its own essence.
On the one hand, the existence is not logically required by
the essence of what is not its own esse—the actual
existence of limited beings (their esse) requires a
creative action by what exists by essence. On the other
hand, the plurality and gradation of the (common) esse
in the existing things requires a single subsistent, exemplar,
cause that has the esse at the highest degree.
[28]
This is how Aquinas proves the necessity
of creation: “all beings apart from
God are not their own being, but are beings by participation.
Therefore it must be that all things which are diversified
by the diverse participation of being, so as to be more or
less perfect, are caused by one First Being, Who possesses
being most perfectly.”
[29]
Our intellectual
knowledge is always in tension between the immediate
knowledge of limited ways of being and the mediate
knowledge of the Being that has in itself the fullness of
being, and that is at the same time (a) the efficient cause,
(b) the exemplary cause, and (c) the final cause of them.
Intellectual curiosity is our tendency to go always beyond
a specific essence toward a fuller understanding of universal
being: our constantly fleeing the (limiting) essence.
[30]
If this is true, Aquinas should have defined
intellectual knowledge with reference to God as its ultimate
object: namely, as the final cause of the knowledge of truth,
or as the end toward which the knowledge of truth ultimately
tends. In point of fact, this is exactly what he did.
He did it in the treatise on law at the exact moment of indicating
the inclination specifically distinguishing man from lower
natures, “Thirdly, there is in man
an inclination to good, according to the nature of his reason,
which nature is proper to him: thus man has a natural inclination
to know the truth about God, and to live in society.”
[31]
At first glance, this passage might appear
strangely reductive with respect to our inclination to know
the truth. However, it is fairly accurate as it refers
our inclination to the truth to its ultimate object and to
our openness to the ens in universali.
3.4. Ens
Universale and Bonum Universale
“For the will
must be commensurate with its object. But the object
of the will is a good grasped by the intellect (bonum intellectum),
as stated above. Therefore, it is of the nature of will
to reach out to whatever the intellect can propose to it under
the aspect of goodness (sub ratione boni).” If our intellect knows
everything in the light of universal being, and so reaches
the knowledge of a first efficient, final and exemplary cause,
Aquinas can legitimately attribute the same scope to our rational
appetite. Thus, to the ens universale corresponds,
on the will’s side, the bonum universale, which determines
the nature and ultimate end of our desire. The passage
we quoted at the beginning—“Because nothing is good except
insofar as it is a likeness and participation of the highest
good, the highest good itself is in some way desired in every
particular good”—should now make more sense: since we know
the goods of this earth in the light of the universal good,
it is impossible for us to know them without, at the same
time, knowing and desiring through them their first cause,
“the highest good itself.”
-
“Someone is Approaching”
It is time now
to go back to the last passage quoted at the beginning:
“To
know that God exists in a general and confused way is implanted
in us by nature, inasmuch as God is man’s beatitude.
For man naturally desires happiness, and what is naturally
desired by man must be naturally known to him. This,
however, is not to know absolutely that God exists; just as
to know that someone is approaching is not the same as to
know that Peter is approaching, even though it is Peter who
is approaching; for many there are who imagine that man’s
perfect good which is happiness, consists in riches, and others
in pleasures, and others in something else.”
It is important
to go back to what this passage means because otherwise Aquinas’
ethical foundation would be, maybe consistent, but a bit odd.
It is obvious that not many people think of God when they
act morally; and everybody has experience of good people who
even do not believe in God. What does it mean, therefore,
that the very knowledge of the good is knowledge and love
of God? As we can see in the passage above, what Aquinas
means is much more nuanced than it might appear at a first
and superficial glance. What we necessarily need when
we know the good is to see that “Someone [the highest good]
is approaching.” This is a necessary (mediate) knowledge
that can be “general and confused,” and that does not mean
“to know God absolutely speaking.” It does mean, however,
that knowledge of the good has an absolute and transcendental
character. This thesis corresponds to what Aquinas says
in ST, I-II, q. 5, a. 8; namely, that “every man necessarily
desires happiness” “according to the general notion of happiness”
(secundum communem rationem beatitudinis); but with
regard to the content of the ultimate end (secundum specialem
rationem quantum ad id in quo beatitudo consistit), “not
all desire happiness.” For Aquinas, in order to know
and to love God “absolutely” we cannot do without “reasoning”
and without morally good behavior.
Now, the idea
that we know the good only when we know that “the highest
good is approaching” is not only extremely interesting, but
also very beautiful. After all, what does it mean to
act morally—i.e., according to conscience—if not to act on
the assumption that what is good transcends both you and me,
and so ought to be done? From this viewpoint, the person
who tries sincerely to act morally without believing in God,
even without realizing it, is on his or her way toward knowing
God “absolutely.” Whereas the immoral person damages
and distorts his or her own intellectual nature by overlapping
the vision of the “highest good” that is approaching with
the selfishness of his or her concupiscence; or, in a sense,
by putting or forcing down the transcendental character of
the good.
Let me conclude
by saying that there are many features of moral experience
that reveal its transcendental character. After all,
moral experience is the paradox of fulfilling oneself by forgetting
or sacrificing oneself. It is the desire for absolute
moral truths, and of an absolute happiness and justice that
are not possible in this world. Many people make strong
moral decisions only when they get to thinking of God.
The so-called “good atheist” ought eventually to find his
way to God. Otherwise he cannot be entirely good, he
will embrace some kind of idolatry, and he will finally frustrate
his nature and the natures of people around him.
|
|