Does the Old Law contain moral
precepts?
It seems that the Old Law does not
contain any moral precepts:
Objection 1: As was
established above (q. 91, a. 4-5), the Old Law is distinct
from the law of nature. But moral precepts belong
to the law of nature. Therefore, they do not belong
to the Old Law.
Objection 2:
Divine law was supposed to assist men in cases where human
reason is deficient; this is clear with those things
pertaining to the Faith that lie beyond human reason. But
man’s reason seems to be sufficient for moral precepts.
Therefore, moral precepts are not part of the Old Law,
which is a type of divine law.
Objection 3:
The Old Law is called “the letter that kills,” as is clear
from 2 Corinthians 3:6. But moral precepts give life and
do not kill—this according to Psalm 118:93 (“I will never
forget Your precepts (iustificationes), because in
them You give me life.”) Therefore, moral precepts do not
belong to the Old Law.
But contrary to this:
Ecclesiasticus 17:9 says, “He gave them discipline and the
law of life for an inheritance.” But ‘discipline’ (disciplina)
pertains to morals, since the Gloss on Hebrews 12:11
(“Every chastisement (disciplina) .....”) says,
“Discipline involves the learning of morals through
difficulties.” Therefore, the Law given by God contained
moral precepts.
I respond:
As is clear from Exodus 20:13 and 15 “You shall not kill
..... You shall not steal”), the Old Law contained certain
moral precepts. And this makes sense. For just as the
main intention of human law is to establish the friendship
of men with one another, so too the intention of divine
law is mainly to establish man’s friendship with God. Now
since, according to Ecclesiasticus 13:19 (“Every beast
loves its like”), likeness is a reason for love, it is
impossible for there to be friendship between man and God,
who is absolutely good, unless men are made good. Hence,
Leviticus 19:2 says, “You will be holy, for I am holy.”
But the goodness of a man is virtue, which makes the one
who has it good. And so precepts of the Old Law had by
all means to be given concerning the acts of the virtues.
And these are the moral precepts of the Law.
Reply to objection 1:
The Old Law is distinguished from the law of nature not in
the sense of being altogether different from it, but in
the sense of adding something to it. For just as grace
presupposes nature, so too divine law must presuppose the
natural law.
Reply to objection 2:
It was appropriate for divine law to provide for man
not only in those matters for which reason is insufficient
for, but also in those matters concerning which man’s
reason can be impeded. Now as far as the moral
precepts are concerned, man’s reason cannot be mistaken
about the universal principle in the case of the most
general precepts of the law of nature, but it can nonetheless,
because of habitual sinning, be blinded with respect
to particular actions. On the other hand, there
are many whose reason goes awry with respect to those
other moral precepts that are like conclusions deduced
from the most general precepts of the law of nature,
with the result that many people are such that their
reason judges as permissible things that are evil in
themselves (mala secundum se). Hence, man
had to be given assistance, through the authority of
divine law, against both kinds of error. Similarly,
in order to prevent the error of human reason that was
occurring with many people, the things proposed to us
for acceptance by faith (credenda) include not
only some that reason cannot attain to, e.g., that God
is three, but also some that right reason can attain
to, e.g., that God is one.
Reply to objection 3:
As Augustine shows in De Spiritu et Littera, the
letter of the law can be an occasion of ‘killing’ even in
the case of the moral precepts, viz., insofar as it
commands what is good without offering the assistance of
grace to fulfill what it commands. |